1 hours 52 minutes 16 seconds
🇬🇧 English
Speaker 1
00:00
The following is a conversation with Jed Buchwald, a professor of history and a philosopher of science at Caltech, interested especially in the development of scientific concepts and the instruments used to create and explore new effects and ideas in science. To support this podcast, please check out our sponsors in the description. This is the Lex Friedman Podcast, and here is my conversation with Jed Buchwald. Does science progress via paradigm shifts and revolutions as philosopher Thomas Kuhn said, or does it progress gradually?
Speaker 1
00:39
What do you think?
Speaker 2
00:41
Well, I got into this field because I was Tom Kuhn's research assistant 50 years ago, 52 years ago. He pulled me into it out of physics instead. So I know his work pretty well.
Speaker 2
00:54
In the years when I was at MIT running an institute, he was then in the philosophy department, used to come over all the time to the talks we held and so on. So what would I say about that? He, of course, developed his ideas a lot over the years. The thing that he's famous for, the structure of Scientific Revolutions, came out in
Speaker 1
01:16
62.
Speaker 2
01:19
And as you just said, it offered an outline for what he called a paradigmatic structure, namely the notion that you have to look at what scientists do as forming a community of investigators, and that they're trying to solve various puzzles, as he would put it, that crop up, figuring out how this works, how that works, and so on. And of course, They don't do it out of the blue, they do it within a certain framework. The framework can be pretty vague.
Speaker 2
01:51
He called it a paradigm. His notion was that eventually they run into troubles or what he called anomalies, that kind of cracks things. Somebody new comes along with a different way of doing it, et cetera. Do I think things work that way?
Speaker 2
02:07
No, not really. Tom and I used to have lengthy discussions about that over the years. I do think there is a common structure that formulates both theoretical and experimental practices. And historians nowadays of science like to refer to scientific work as what scientists practice.
Speaker 2
02:30
It's almost craftsman-like. They can usually adapt in various ways. And I can give you all kinds of examples of that. I once wrote a book on the origins of wave theory of light, and that is 1 of the paradigmatic examples that Tom used, only it didn't work that way exactly, because he thought that what happened was that the wave theory ran into trouble with a certain phenomenon which it couldn't crack.
Speaker 2
03:05
Well, it turned out that in fact historically that phenomenon was actually not relevant later on to the wave theory. And when the wave theory came in, the alternative to it which had prevailed, which was Newton's views, light is particles, that it seemed couldn't explain what the wave theory could explain. Again, not true. Not true.
Speaker 2
03:32
Much more complex than that. The wave theory offered the opportunity to deploy novel experimental and mathematical structures which gave younger scientists, mathematicians and others, the opportunity to effect, manufacture, make new sorts of devices. It's not that the alternative couldn't sort of explain these things, but it never was able to generate them de novo as novelties. In other words, if you think of it as something scientists wanna progress in the sense of finding new stuff to solve, then I think what often happens is, is that it's not so much that the prevailing view can't crack something as that it doesn't give you the opportunity to do new stuff.
Speaker 1
04:23
When you say new stuff, are we referring to experimental science here or new stuff in the space of new theories?
Speaker 2
04:29
Could be both. Could be both, actually.
Speaker 1
04:32
So how does that, can you maybe elaborate a
Speaker 2
04:34
little bit on the story of the wave? Sure. The prevailing view of light, at least in France where the wave theory really first took off, although it had been introduced in England by Thomas Young, The prevailing theory dates back to Newton, that light is a stream of particles and that refraction and reflection involve sort of repulsive and attractive forces that deflect and bend the paths of these particles.
Speaker 2
05:03
Newton was not able successfully to deal with the phenomenon of what happens when light goes past a knife's edge or a sharp edge, what we now call diffraction. He had cooked up something about it that no mathematical structure could be applied. Thomas Young first, but really this guy named Augustin Fresnel in France, deployed, In Fresnel's case, rather advanced calculus forms of mathematics which enabled computations to be done and observations to be melded with these computations in a way that you could not do or see how to do with Newton. Did that mean that the Newtonian explanation of what goes on in diffraction fails?
Speaker 2
05:53
Not really. You can actually make it work, but you can't generate anything new out of it. Whereas using the mathematics of wave optics in respect to a particular phenomenon called polarization, which ironically was discovered by partisans of Newton's way of doing things, you were able to generate devices which reflect light and crystals, do various things that the Newtonian way could accommodate only after the fact. They couldn't generate it from the beginning.
Speaker 2
06:33
And so if you want to be somebody who is working a novel vein, which increasingly becomes the case with people who become what we now call physicists in the 1820s, 30s, and 40s in particular, then that's the direction you're gonna go. But there were holdouts until the 1850s.
Speaker 1
06:55
I wanna try to elaborate on the nature of the disagreement you have with Thomas Kuhn. So do you still believe in paradigm shifts? Do you still see that there's ideas that really have a transformational effect on science?
Speaker 1
07:09
The nature of the disagreement has to do with how those paradigm shifts come to be?
Speaker 2
07:15
How they come to be and how they change. I certainly think they exist. How strong they may be at any given time is maybe not quite as powerful as Tom thought in general, although towards the end of his life, he was beginning to develop different modifications of his original way of thinking.
Speaker 2
07:37
But I don't think that the changes happened quite so neatly, if you will, in reaction to novel experimental observations. They can be much more complex than that.
Speaker 1
07:53
In terms of neatness, how much of science progresses by individual lone geniuses and how much by the messy collaboration of competing and cooperating humans?
Speaker 2
08:12
I don't think you can cut that with a knife to say it's this percent and that percent. It's almost always the case that there are 1 or 2 or maybe 3 individuals who are sort of central to what goes on when things begin to shift. Are they inevitably and solely responsible for what then begins to happen in a major way?
Speaker 2
08:45
I think not. It depends. You can go very far back with this, even into antiquity to see what goes on. The major locus we always talk about from the beginning is if you're talking about Galileo's work on motion, for example, were there ways of accommodating it that others could adapt to without buying into the whole scheme?
Speaker 2
09:12
Yes. Did it eventually evolve and start convincing people because you could also do other things with it that you couldn't otherwise do? Also yes. Let me give you an example.
Speaker 2
09:26
The great French mathematician, philosopher Descartes, who was a mechanical philosopher, he believed the world was matter in motion. He never thought much of what Galileo had done in respect to motion because he thought, well, at best it's some sort of approximative scheme or something like that. But 1 of his initial, I wouldn't call him a disciple, but follower who then broke with him in a number of ways, was a man named Christian Huygens, who was along with Newton, 1 of the 2 greatest scientists of the 17th century. Huygens is older than Newton.
Speaker 2
10:04
And Huygens nicely deployed Galilean relationships in respect to motion to develop all sorts of things, including the first pendulum-governed clock, and even figured out how to build 1 which keeps perfect time, except it didn't work, but he had the mathematical structure for it.
Speaker 1
10:27
How well known is Huygens? Oh, very well known. Should I know him well?
Speaker 2
10:31
Yes, you should. Interesting. You should definitely know him well.
Speaker 1
10:34
No, no, no, no, no. Can we define should here? Okay.
Speaker 1
10:38
Because I don't. Right. So is this should like, Yeah, can you define should?
Speaker 2
10:48
Should means this, if you had taken up to a second year of physics courses, you would have heard his name because 1 of the fundamental principles in optics is called Huygens principle. Okay. Okay?
Speaker 1
11:04
Yeah, so I have and I have heard his name.
Speaker 2
11:07
There you go.
Speaker 1
11:07
No, but I don't remember.
Speaker 2
11:08
But you don't remember.
Speaker 1
11:09
So I mean, there's a very different thing between names attached to principles and laws and so on that you sometimes let go of, you just remember the equations of the principles themselves and the personalities of science. And there's certain personalities, certain human beings that stand out. And that's why there's a sense to which the lone inventor, the lone scientist is the way I personally, I mean, I think a lot of people think about the history of science, is these lone geniuses.
Speaker 1
11:41
Without them, the sense is, if you remove Newton from the picture, if you remove Galileo from the picture, then science would, there's almost a feeling like it would just have stopped there. Or at the very least, there's a feeling like it would take much longer to develop the things that were developed. Is that a silly way to look at the history of science.
Speaker 2
12:01
That's not entirely incorrect, I suppose. I find it difficult to believe that had Galileo not existed, that eventually someone like Huygens, for instance, given the context of the time, what was floating around in the belief structure concerning the nature of the world and so on, the developments in mathematics and whatnot, that sooner or later, whether it would have been exactly the same or not, I cannot say, but would things have evolved? Yes.
Speaker 1
12:45
If we look at the long arc of history of science, from back when we were in the caves trying to knock 2 rocks together, or maybe make a basic tool,
Speaker 2
13:00
to
Speaker 1
13:00
a long time from now, many centuries from now when human civilization finally destroys itself. If we look at that history, and imagine you're a historian at the end, like with the fire of the apocalypse coming upon us, and you look back at this time in the 21st century, how far along are we on that arc? Do you sense?
Speaker 1
13:25
Have we invented and discovered everything that's to be discovered, or are we at like below 1%?
Speaker 2
13:31
Well, it's-
Speaker 1
13:32
You're gonna get a lot of absurd questions today.
Speaker 2
13:35
I apologize. It's a lugubrious picture you're painting there.
Speaker 1
13:39
I don't even know what the word lugubrious
Speaker 2
13:42
is, but I love it.
Speaker 1
13:43
Lugubrious.
Speaker 2
13:46
Well, let me try and separate the question of whether we're all going to die in an apocalypse in several hundred years or not from the question of where science may be sitting. Take that as an assumption. Okay.
Speaker 2
14:02
I find that hard to say. And I find it hard to say because in the deepest sense of the term, as it's usually deployed by philosophers of science today. I'm not fundamentally a realist. That is to say, I think our access to the inner workings of nature is inevitably mediated by what we can do with the materials and factors around us.
Speaker 2
14:39
We can probe things in various ways. Does that mean that I don't think that the standard model in quantum electrodynamics is in, of course not. I wouldn't even dream of saying such a thing. It can do a lot, especially when it comes to figuring out what's happening in very large, expensive particle accelerators.
Speaker 2
15:02
And applying results in cosmology and so on as well. Do I think that we have inevitably probed the depths of reality through this? I do not agree with Steven Weinberg, who thinks we have, about such things. Do I, on the other hand, think that the way in which science has been moving for the last 100 years, physics in particular is what I have in mind, will continue on the same course.
Speaker 2
15:35
In that sense, I don't, because we're not going to be building bigger and bigger and more and more expensive machines to rip apart particles in various ways. In which case, what are physicists gonna do? They'll turn their attention to other aspects. There are all sorts of things we've never explained about the material world.
Speaker 2
15:57
We don't have theories that go beyond a certain point for all sorts of things. We can, can we for example, start with the standard model and work our way up all the way to chemical transformations? You can make an argument about it and you can justify things, but that's in chemistry, that's not the way people work. They work with much higher level quantum mechanical relationships and so on.
Speaker 2
16:28
So this notion of the deep theory to explain everything is a longstanding belief, which goes back pretty far, although I think it only takes its fullest form sometime in towards the end of the 19th century.
Speaker 1
16:45
So maybe we just speak to that. You're referring to a hope, a dream, a reality of coming up with a theory of everything that explains everything. So there's a very specific thing that that currently means in physics, is the unification of the laws of physics.
Speaker 1
17:02
But I'm sure in antiquity or before, it meant maybe something else, or is it always about physics? Because I mean, I think as you've kind of implied, in physics there's a sense, once you get to the theory of everything, you've understood everything. But there's a very deep sense in which you've actually understood not very much at all. You've understood at that particular level how things work, but you don't understand how the abstractions on top of abstractions form, all the way to the chemistry, to the human mind, and the human societies, and all those kinds of things.
Speaker 1
17:35
So maybe you can speak to the theory of everything and its history and comment on what the heck does that even mean, a theory of everything.
Speaker 2
17:43
Well, I don't think you can go back that far with something like that, maybe at best to the 17th century. If you go back all the way in antiquity, there are of course discussions about the nature of the world. But First of all, you have to recognize that the manipulative character of physics and chemistry, the probing of, let me put it this way.
Speaker 2
18:16
We assume and have assumed for a long time, I'll come back to when in a moment, that if I take a little device which is really complicatedly made out of all kinds of things and I put a piece of some material in it, and I monkey around with it and do all kinds of unnatural things to it, things that wouldn't happen naturally, and I find out how it behaves and whatnot. And then I try and make an argument about how that really applies even in the natural world without any artificial structures and so on. That's not a belief that was widely held by pretty much anyone until sometime maybe in the 1500s. And when it was first held, it was held by people we now call alchemists.
Speaker 1
19:09
So alchemy was the first, the early days of the theory of everything, of a dream of a theory of everything.
Speaker 2
19:14
I would put it a little differently. I think it's more along the way a dream that by probing nature in artificially constructed ways, we can find out what's going on deep down there.
Speaker 1
19:32
So that's distinct from science being an observing thing where you observe nature and you study nature. You're talking about probing, like messing with nature to understand it.
Speaker 2
19:45
Indeed I am, but that of course is the very essence of experimental science. You have to manipulate nature to find out things about it, and then you have to convince others that you haven't so manipulated it that what you've done is to produce what amounts to fake, artifactual behavior that doesn't really hold purely naturally. So where are we today in your sense to jump around a little bit with the theory of everything?
Speaker 1
20:21
Maybe a quick kind of sense you have about the journey in the world of physics that we're taking towards the theory of everything.
Speaker 2
20:31
Well, I'm of course not a practicing physicist. I mean, I was trained in physics at Princeton a long time ago. Until Thomas Kuhn stole you away.
Speaker 2
20:41
More or less. I was taking graduate courses in those days in general relativity. I was an undergraduate, but I moved up and then I took a course with him.
Speaker 1
20:50
Well, you made the mistake of being compelled by charismatic philosophers and never looked back.
Speaker 2
20:57
I suppose so in a way. And from what I understand, talking especially to my friends at Caltech, like Kip Thorne and others, the fundamental notion is that actually the laws that even at the deepest level we can sort of divine and work with in the universe that we inhabit are perhaps quite unique to this particular universe as it formed at the Big Bang. The question is, how deep does it go?
Speaker 2
21:39
If you are very mathematically inclined, the prevailing notion for several decades now has been what's called string theory, but that has not been able to figure a way to generate probative experimental evidence, although it's pretty good apparently at accommodating things. And then the question is, what's before the Big Bang? Or actually the word before doesn't mean anything given the nature of time, but why do we have the laws that prevail in our universe? Well, there is a notion that those laws prevail in our universe because if they didn't, we wouldn't be here.
Speaker 1
22:30
That's a bit of a cyclical, but nevertheless, a compelling definition. And there's all kinds of things like the, it seems like the unification of those laws could be discovered by looking inside of a black hole, because you get both the general relativity and the quantum mechanics, quantum field theory in there. Experimentally, of course, there's a lot of interesting ideas.
Speaker 1
22:51
We can't really look close to the Big Bang, can't look that far back. There's Caltech and MIT, LIGO, looking at gravitational waves, perhaps allows us to march backwards and so on. Yeah, it's a really exciting space. And there's of course, the theory of everything, like with a lot of things in science, captivates the dreams of those who are perhaps completely outside of science.
Speaker 1
23:14
It's the dream of discovering the key to the nature of how everything works. And that feels deeply human. That's perhaps the thing, the basic elements of what makes up a scientist in the end is that curiosity, that longing to understand. Let me ask, you mentioned a disagreement with Weinberg on reality.
Speaker 1
23:43
Could you elaborate a little bit?
Speaker 2
23:45
Well, obviously I don't disagree with Steve Weinberg on physics itself. I wouldn't know enough to even begin to do that. And clearly, he's 1 of the founders of the standard model and so on, and it works to a level of accuracy that no physical theory has ever worked at before.
Speaker 2
24:06
I suppose the question in my mind is something that in 1 way could go back to the philosopher Immanuel Kant in the 18th century, namely, can we really ever convince ourselves that we have come to grips with something that is not in itself knowable to us by our senses or even except in the most remote way through the complex instruments that we make as to what it is that underlies everything. Can we corral it with mathematics and experimental structures? Yes. Do I think that a particular way of corralling nature will inevitably play itself out?
Speaker 2
25:01
I don't know. It always has. I'll put it to you that way.
Speaker 1
25:08
So the basic question is, can we know reality? Is that the Kant question, Is that the Weinberg question? We humans.
Speaker 1
25:24
Okay. With our brains. Right. Can we comprehend reality?
Speaker 1
25:30
Sounds like a very trippy question because a lot of it rests on definitions of no and comprehend and reality, but get to the bottom of it. Like it's turtles on top of turtles, can we get to the bottom turtle?
Speaker 2
25:45
Well, Maybe I can put it to you this way, in a way that I often begin discussions in a class on the history of science and so on, and say, I'm looking at you. Yes. You are in fact a figment of my imagination.
Speaker 2
26:11
You have a messed up imagination, yes. Well, what do I mean by that? If I were a dragonfly looking at you, whatever my nervous system would form by way of a perceptual structure would clearly be utterly different from what my brain and perceptual system altogether is forming when I look at you. Who's right?
Speaker 2
26:48
Is it me or the dragonfly?
Speaker 1
26:54
Well the dragonfly is certainly very impressive, so I don't know. But yes, it's the observer matters. What is that supposed to tell us about objective reality?
Speaker 2
27:08
Well, I think it means that it's very difficult to get beyond the constructs that our perceptual system is leading us to. When we make apparatus and devices and so on, we're still making things, the results of which or the outputs of which we process perceptually in various ways. And an analogy I like to use with students sometimes is this.
Speaker 2
27:38
All right, they all have their laptops open in front of them, of course, okay? And I've sent them something to read. And I say, okay, click on it and open it up. So PDF opens up.
Speaker 2
27:51
I said, what are you looking at? He said, well, I'm looking at the paper that you sent me. I said, no, you're not. What you're looking at is a stream of light coming off LEDs or LCDs coming off a screen.
Speaker 2
28:06
And I said, what happens when you use your mouse and move that fake piece of paper on the screen around? What are you doing? You're not moving a piece of paper around, are you? You're moving a construct around, a construct that's being processed so that our perceptual system can interact with it in the way we interact with pieces of paper.
Speaker 2
28:30
But it's not real.
Speaker 1
28:34
So are there things outside of the reach of science? Can you maybe, as an example, talk about consciousness? I'm asking for a friend, trying to figure this thing out.
Speaker 2
28:49
Well, boy, I mean, I read a fair bit about that, but I certainly can't really say much about it. I'm a materialist in the deepest sense of the term. I don't think there is anything out there except material structures which interact in various ways.
Speaker 2
29:14
Do I think, for example, that this bottle of water is conscious? No, I do not. Although, how would I know? I can't talk to it.
Speaker 1
29:25
But, so what do? It's a hypothesis you have. It's an opinion, an educated opinion that may be very wrong.
Speaker 2
29:31
Well, I know that you're conscious because I can interact directly with you. But am I? Well, unless you're a figment of my imagination, of course.
Speaker 1
29:39
No, or I'm a robot that's able to generate the illusion of consciousness effectively enough to facilitate a good conversation. Because we humans do want to pretend that we're talking to other conscious beings because that's how we respect them. If it's not conscious, we don't respect them.
Speaker 1
29:56
We're not good at talking to robots.
Speaker 2
29:57
That's true. Of course, we generalize from our own inner sense, which is the kind of thing Descartes said from the beginning. We generalize from that, but I do think that consciousness must be something, whatever it is, that occurs as a result of some particular organizational structure of material elements.
Speaker 1
30:22
Does materialism mean that it's all within the reach of science?
Speaker 2
30:28
My sense would be that especially as neuroscience progresses more and more. At Caltech, we just built a whole neuroscience arena and so on. And as more knowledge is gained about the ways in which animals, when they behave, what patterns show up at various parts of the brain and nervous system, and perhaps extending it to humans eventually as well, we'll get more of a handle on what brain activity is associated with experiences that we have as humans.
Speaker 2
31:13
Can we move from the brain activity to the experiences in terms of our, no, you can't. Perception is perception.
Speaker 1
31:24
That's a hypothesis once again. Maybe the, Maybe consciousness is just 1 of the laws of physics that's yet to be discovered. Maybe it permeates all matter.
Speaker 1
31:37
Maybe it's as simple as trying to plug it in and plug into the ability to generate and control that kind of law of physics that would crack open, where we would understand that the bottle of water is in fact conscious, just much less conscious than us humans, and then we would be able to then generate beings that are more conscious.
Speaker 2
32:02
Well, that'll be unfortunate. I'd have to stop drinking the water after that.
Speaker 1
32:06
Every time you take a sip, there's a little bit of a suffering going on. Right. What to use the most interesting, beautiful moments in the history of science.
Speaker 1
32:17
What stands out? And then we can pull at that thread.
Speaker 2
32:22
Right. Well, I like to think of events that have a major impact and involve both beautiful conceptual, mathematical, if we're talking physical structures work, and are associated as well with probing experimental situations. So among my favorites is 1 of the most famous, which was the young Isaac Newton's work with the colors produced when you pass sunlight through a prism. And why do I like that?
Speaker 2
33:03
It's not profoundly mathematical in 1 sense. It doesn't need it initially. It needs the following though, which begins to show you, I think, a little bit about what gets involved when you've got a smart individual who's trying to monkey around with stuff and finds new things about it. First let me say that the notion, the prevailing notion going back to antiquity was that colors are produced in a sense by modifying or tinting white light, that they're modifications of white light.
Speaker 2
33:37
In other words, the colors are not in the sunlight in any way. Now, what Newton did following experiments done by Descartes before him who came to very different conclusions, he took a prism. You might ask, where do you get prisms in the 1660s? It's a
Speaker 1
33:56
good question.
Speaker 2
33:58
County fairs. They were very popular. They were pretty crude with bubbles in them and everything, but they produced colors so you could buy them at county fairs and things, very popular.
Speaker 1
34:08
Oh, so they were modifying the white light to create colors.
Speaker 2
34:11
Well, they were creating colors from it, well known. And what he did was the following. He was by this time, even though he's very young, a very good mathematician.
Speaker 2
34:24
And he could use the then known laws for how light behaves when it goes through glass to calculate what should happen if you took light from the sun, passed it from a hole, through a little hole, then hit the prism, goes out of the prism, strikes a wall a long distance away and makes a splash of light. Never mind the colors for a moment, makes a splash of light there. He was very smart. First of all, he abstracts from the colors themselves, even though that's what everybody's paying attention to initially.
Speaker 2
34:59
Because what he knows is this, he knows that if you take this prism and you turn it to a certain particular angle that he knew what it should be because he could calculate things. Very few other people in Europe at the time could calculate things like he could. That if you turn the prism to that particular angle, then the sun, which is of course a circle, when its light passes through this little hole and then into the prism on the far distant wall should still make a circle, but it doesn't. It makes a very long image.
Speaker 2
35:40
And this led him to a very different conception of light, indicating that there are different types of light in the sunlight. Now to go beyond that, what's particularly interesting I think is the following. When he published this paper, which got him into a controversy, He really didn't describe at all what he did. He just gave you some numbers.
Speaker 2
36:06
Now I just told you that you had to set this prism at a certain angle, right? You would think, because we do have his notes and so on, You would think that he took some kind of complicated measuring device to set the prism. He didn't. He held it in his hand, that's all, and he twiddled it around.
Speaker 2
36:29
What was he doing? It turns out that when you twiddle the prism around at the point where you should get a circle from a circle, it also is the place where the image does not move very fast.
Speaker 1
36:43
So
Speaker 2
36:43
if you want to get close to there, you just twiddle it. This is manipulative experimentation taking advantage through his mathematical knowledge of the inherent inaccuracies that let you come to exact conclusions regardless of the built-in problematics of measurement. He's the only 1 I know of doing anything like that
Speaker 1
37:11
at the time. Yeah. Well, even still, there's very few people that are able to have, to calculate as well as you did, to be a theoretician and an experimentalist, like in the same moment.
Speaker 1
37:26
Right?
Speaker 2
37:27
It's true, although until the, really the well into the 20th century, maybe the beginning of the 20th century, really, most of the most significant experimental results produced in the 1800s, which laid the foundations for light, electricity, electrodynamics, and so on, even hydrodynamics and whatnot, were also produced by people who were both excellent calculators, very talented mathematicians, and good with their hands experimentally.
Speaker 1
38:11
And then that led to the 21st century with Enrico Fermi that 1 of the last people that was able to do that, both of those things very well, and that he built a little device called an atomic bomb that has some positives and negatives. Depending on your perspective. Well, Right,
Speaker 2
38:30
of course that actually did involve some pretty large scale elaborate equipment too.
Speaker 1
38:35
Well, holding a prism in your hands,
Speaker 2
38:38
same thing. Right, no.
Speaker 1
38:40
What's the controversy that you got into with that paper when you published it?
Speaker 2
38:45
Well, in a number of ways, it's a complicated story. There was a very talented character known as a mechanic. Mechanic means somebody who was a craftsman who could build and make really good stuff.
Speaker 2
39:02
And he was very talented. His name was Robert Hooke. And he was the guy who, at the weekly meetings of the Royal Society in London, and Newton's not in London, he's at Cambridge, he's a young guy, he would demonstrate new things. And he was very clever.
Speaker 2
39:18
And he had written a book, in fact, called The Micrographia, which by the way, he used a microscope to make the first depictions of things like a fly's eye, the structure of, and it had a big influence. And in there, he also talked about light. And so he had a different view of light. And when he read what Newton wrote, he had a double reaction.
Speaker 2
39:41
On the 1 hand, he said, anything in there that is correct, I already knew. And anything that I didn't already know is probably not right anyway.
Speaker 1
39:54
Got to love egos. Okay, can we just step back? Can you say Who was Isaac Newton?
Speaker 1
40:02
What are the things he contributed to this world in the space of ideas? Wow.
Speaker 2
40:11
Who was he? He was born in
Speaker 1
40:16
1642
Speaker 2
40:20
and near the small town of Grantham in England. In fact, the house he was born in and that his mother died in is still there and can be visited. His father died before he was born, and his mother eventually remarried a man named Reverend Smith, whom Newton did not like at all, because Reverend Smith took his mother away to live with him a few miles away, leaving Newton to be brought up more or less by his grandmother over there.
Speaker 2
40:58
And he had huge resentment about that his whole life.
Speaker 1
41:02
I think that gives you a little inkling that a little bit of trauma in childhood, maybe a complicated father-son relationship can be useful to create a good scientist.
Speaker 2
41:13
Could be, although this case it would be right, the absent father, non-father relationship, so to speak. He was known as a kid, little that we do know, for being very clever about flying kites. There are stories about him putting candles and flying kites and scaring the living devil out of people at night by doing that and things like that, making things.
Speaker 2
41:40
Most of the physicists and natural philosophers I've dealt with actually as children were very fond of making and playing with things. I can't think of 1 I know of who wasn't actually. Very good with their hands and whatnot. His mother wanted him to take over the manor.
Speaker 2
42:07
It was a kind of farming manor. They were the class of what are known as yeomans. There are stories that he wasn't very good at that. 1 day, 1 of the stories is he's sitting out in the field and the cows come home without him and he doesn't know what's going...
Speaker 2
42:22
Anyway, add relatives and he manages to get to Cambridge, sent to Cambridge because he's known to be smart. He's read books that he got from local dignitaries and some relatives. And he goes there as what's known as a subsizer. What does that mean?
Speaker 2
42:40
Well, it's not too pleasant. Basically, a subsizer was a student who had to clean the bedpans of the richer kids. That didn't last too long. He makes his way and he becomes absorbed in some of the new ways of thinking that are being talked about on the parts of Descartes and others as well.
Speaker 2
43:04
There's also the traditional curriculum which he follows. And we have his notes. We have his student notebooks and so on. We can see gradually this young man's mind focusing and coming to grips with deeper questions of the nature of the world and perception even and how we know things, and also probing and learning mathematical structures to such an extent that he builds on some of the investigations that had been done in the period before him to create the foundations of a way of investigating processes that happen and change continuously instead of by leaps and bounds and so on, forming the foundation of what we now call the calculus.
Speaker 1
43:52
Yeah. So can you maybe just paint a little bit of a picture, you've already started, of what were the things that bothered him the most, that stood out to him the most about the traditional curriculum, about the way people saw the world? You mentioned discrete versus continuous. Is there something where he began thinking in a revolutionary way.
Speaker 1
44:18
Because it's fascinating. Most of us go to college, Cambridge or otherwise, and we just kind of take what we hear as gospel, right? Like not gospel, but as like facts. You don't begin to sort of see, how can I expand on this aggressively?
Speaker 1
44:39
How can I challenge everything that I hear? Like rigorously, mathematically, through the, I mean, I don't even know how rigorous the mathematics was at that point. I'm sure it was geometry and so on, no calculus, huh? There are
Speaker 2
44:55
elements of what turned into the calculus that predate Newton, but.
Speaker 1
45:01
How much rigor was there? How much? Well, rigor, no.
Speaker 1
45:04
And then, of course, no scientific method Not really. I mean somewhat like I mean appreciation of data
Speaker 2
45:13
That is a separate question from a question of method Appreciation of data is a significant question as to what you do with data. There's lots of things you're asking.
Speaker 1
45:23
I apologize. So maybe let's backtrack in the first question is was there something that was bothering him that he especially thought he could contribute or work on?
Speaker 2
45:34
Well, of course, we can't go back and talk to him, but we do have these student notebooks. There's 2 of them. One's called the Philosophical Questions and the other is called the Wastebook.
Speaker 2
45:45
The philosophical questions has discussions of the nature of reality and various issues concerning it. And the waste book has things that have to do with motion in various ways, what happens in collisions and things of that sort. And It's a complicated story. But what's among the things that I think are interesting is he took notes in the philosophical questions on stuff that was traditionally given to you in the curriculums going back several hundred years, namely on what scholars refer to as scholastic or neo-scholastic ways of thinking about the world, dating back to the reformulation of Aristotle in the Middle Ages by Thomas Aquinas in the church.
Speaker 2
46:34
This is a totally different way of thinking about things, which actually connects to something we were saying a moment ago. For instance, so I'm wearing a blue shirt, and I will sometimes ask students, where is the blue? And they'll usually say, well, it's in your shirt. And then some of them get clever and they say, well, no, you know, light is striking it, photons are re-emitted, they strike the back of your retina, and et cetera, et cetera.
Speaker 2
47:01
And I said, yes. What that means is that the blue is actually an artifact of our perceptual system considered as the percept of blue. It's not out there, it's in here. That's not how things were thought about well into the 16th century.
Speaker 2
47:23
The general notion dating back even to Aristotelian antiquity and formalized by the 12th century at Paris, Oxford and elsewhere is that qualities are there in the world. They're not in us. We have senses and our senses can be wrong. You know, You could go blind, things like that.
Speaker 2
47:50
But if they're working properly, you get the actual qualities of the world. Now, that break, which is occurring towards the end of the 16th century and is most visible in Descartes is the break between conceiving that the qualities of the world are very different from the qualities that we perceive. That In fact, the qualities of the world consist almost entirely in shapes of various kinds and maybe hard particles or whatever, but not colors, not sounds, Not smells, not softness and hardness. They're not in the world, they're in us.
Speaker 2
48:37
That break, Newton is picking up as he reads Descartes. He's gonna disagree with a lot in Descartes. But that break, he is, among other things, picking up very strongly. And that underlies a lot of the way he works later on when he becomes skeptical of the evidence provided by the senses.
Speaker 2
49:00
Yeah,
Speaker 1
49:01
that's actually, I don't know, the way you're describing it is so powerful. It just makes me realize how liberating that is as a scientist, as somebody who's trying to understand reality, that our senses is just, our senses are not to be trusted. That reality is to be investigated through tools that are beyond our senses.
Speaker 2
49:27
Yes. Or that improve our senses.
Speaker 1
49:30
Or improve our senses.
Speaker 2
49:32
In some ways.
Speaker 1
49:34
That's pretty powerful. I mean, that is, for a human being, that's like Einstein level. For a human being to realize I can't trust my own senses at that time, that's pretty trippy.
Speaker 2
49:53
It's coming in, it's coming in, and I think it arises probably a fair number of decades before that, perhaps in part with all chemical experimentation and manipulations, that you have to go through elaborate structures to produce things and ways you think about it. But let me give you an example that I think you might find interesting because it's from, it involves that guy named Hook that Newton had an argument with. And he had lots of arguments with Hook, although Hook was a very clever guy and gave him some things that stimulated him later.
Speaker 2
50:34
Anyway, Hooke, who was argumentative, and he really was convinced that the only way to gain real knowledge of nature is through carefully constructed devices. And he was an expert mechanic, if you will, at building such things. Now there was a rather wealthy man in Danzig by the name of Hevelius, Latinized name. He was a brewer in town.
Speaker 2
51:07
And he had become fascinated with the telescope. This is
Speaker 1
51:12
30
Speaker 2
51:13
years or so, 20 or 30 years after the telescope had moved out and become more common. And he built a large observatory on the top of his brewery, actually, and working with his wife, they used these very elaborately constructed brass and metal instruments to make observations of positions of the stars. And he published a whole new catalog of where the stars are.
Speaker 2
51:42
And he claimed it was incredibly accurate. He claimed it was so accurate that nothing had ever come close to it. Hook reads this and he says, wait a minute. You didn't use a telescope here of any kind because what's the point unless you do something to the telescope, all you see are dots with stars.
Speaker 2
52:01
You just use your eye. Your eyes can't be that good. It's impossible. So what did Hooke do to prove this?
Speaker 2
52:08
He said, what you should have done is you should have put a little device in the telescope that lets you measure distances between these dots. You didn't do that, and because you didn't, there's no way you could have been that good. At 2 successive meetings of the Royal Society, he hauls the members out into the courtyard, and he takes a card, and he makes successive black and white stripes on the card. And he pastes the card up on a wall and he takes them 1 by 1.
Speaker 2
52:39
He says, now move back looking at it, presumably with 1 eye, until you can't tell the black ones from the white stripes." He says, that I can then measure the distance, I can see the angles, I can give a number then for what is the best possible, what we would call perceptual acuity of human vision. And it turned out, he thought, to be something like 10 or more times worse than this guy Hevelius had claimed. So obviously, he says, Hoke, Hevelius... Well, years ago, I calculated Hevelius's numbers and so on using modern tables from NASA and so on, and they are even more accurate than Hevelius claimed.
Speaker 2
53:28
And worse than that, The Royal Society sent a young astronomer named Halley over to Danzig to work with him, and Halley writes back, and he says, I couldn't believe it, but I could, he taught me how to do it, and I could get just as good as he, how is it possible? Well, here, this shows you something very interesting about experiments, perception, and everything else. Hooke was right, but he was also wrong. He was wrong for the right reasons, and he was right for the wrong reasons.
Speaker 2
54:00
And what do I mean by that? What he actually found was the number for what we now call 2020 vision. He was right. You can't tell, except a few people, much better than that.
Speaker 2
54:17
But he was observing the wrong thing. What Hevelius was observing was a bright dot, a star moving past a pointer. Our eyes are rather similar to frogs eyes. You know, I'm sure you've heard the story, if I hold a dead fly on a string in front of a frog and don't move it, the frog pays no attention.
Speaker 2
54:42
As soon as I move the fly, the frog immediately tongue lats out because the visual system of the frog responds to motion. So does ours. And our acuity for distinguishing motion from statics, 5 or more times better.
Speaker 1
55:00
Yeah, that's fascinating. Damn. And of course, I mean, maybe you can comment on their understanding of the human perceptual system at the time was probably really terrible.
Speaker 1
55:14
Like, yeah, like I've recently been working with, just almost as a fun side thing with vision scientists and peripheral vision, it's a beautiful complex mess, that whole thing. We still don't understand all the weird ways that human perception works. And they were probably terrible at it. They probably didn't have any conception of peripheral vision or the fovea or, I mean, basically anything.
Speaker 2
55:41
They had some, I mean, because actually it was Newton himself who probed a lot of this. For instance, Newton, the young Newton, trying to work his way around what's going on with colors, wanted to try and distinguish colors that occur through natural processes out there, And colors that are a result of our eyes not operating right. So you know what he did?
Speaker 2
56:05
It's a famous thing. He took a stick and he stuck that stick under his lower eyelid and pushed up on his eyeball. And what that did would produce colored circles at diametrically opposite positions of the stick in the eyeball, and he moved it around to see how they moved, trying to distinguish. Legit.
Speaker 2
56:29
Right? I always have to tell my students don't do this, but... Or do it if you want to be great
Speaker 1
56:36
and remembered by human history. There's a lot of equivalent to sticking to your eye in modern day that May pay off in the end. Okay.
Speaker 1
56:51
As a small aside, is the Newton and the Apple story true?
Speaker 2
56:55
No. Was
Speaker 1
56:56
it a different fruit?
Speaker 2
57:00
As a colleague of mine named Simon Schaffer in England once said on a NOVA program that we were both on, the role of fruit in the history of science has been vastly exaggerated.
Speaker 1
57:13
Okay, so Was there any, I mean, to zoom out, moments of epiphany? Is there something to moments of epiphany? Or again, this is the paradigm shift versus the gradualism.
Speaker 2
57:27
There is a shift. It's a much more complex 1 than that. As it happens, a colleague of mine and I are writing a paper right now on 1 of the aspects of these things based on the work that many of our colleagues have done over the last 30 and 40 years.
Speaker 2
57:49
Let me try and see if I could put it to you this way. Newton, until the early 1670s, and probably really until a fair time after that, first of all, was not very interested in questions of motion. He was working actually in all chemical relationships or what is called by historians, chymistry, a kind of early modern chemical structure. Colleagues of ours at Indiana have even reproduced the amalgams that, anyway.
Speaker 2
58:25
His way of thinking about motion involved a certain set of relationships, which was not conducive to any application that would yield computationally direct results for things like planetary motions, which he wasn't terribly interested in anyway. He enters a correspondence with his original nemesis, Robert Hooke, and Hooke says, well, have you ever thought about, and then Hooke tells him a certain way you might think about it. And when Newton hears that, he recognizes that there is a way to inject time that would enable him to solve certain problems. It's not that there was anything he thought before that was contrary to that way of thinking.
Speaker 2
59:21
It's just that that particular technical insight was not something that for a lot of reasons that are complex had never occurred to him at all. And that sent him a different way of thinking. But to answer your question about the Apple business, which is always about gravity and the moon and all of that being... No.
Speaker 2
59:45
The reason there is that the idea that what goes on here in the neighborhood of the Earth and what goes on at the Moon, let us say, never mind the Sun and the planet, is that we're all in the same place.
Omnivision Solutions Ltd